Dictionary Definition
rationality
Noun
1 the state of having good sense and sound
judgment; "his rationality may have been impaired"; "he had to rely
less on reason than on rousing their emotions" [syn: reason, reasonableness]
2 the quality of being consistent with or based
on logic [syn: rationalness]
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Noun
- Sanity, good sense.
- His sudden loss of rationality was brought on by excess drink.
- Objectivity,
thoughtfulness.
- Such a discussion deserves rationality, not emotion a gut reaction.
Derived terms
Extensive Definition
Rationality as a term is related to the idea of
reason, a word which
following Webster's may be
derived as much from older terms referring to thinking itself as from giving
an account or an explanation. This lends the term a dual aspect.
One aspect associates it with comprehension, intelligence, or
inference, particularly when an inference is drawn in ordered ways
(thus a syllogism is a
rational argument in this sense). The other part associates
rationality with explanation, understanding or justification,
particularly if it provides a ground or a motive. 'Irrational',
therefore, is defined as that which is not endowed with reason or
understanding.
A logical
argument is often described as "rational" if it is logically valid. However,
rationality is a much broader term than logic, as it includes
"uncertain but sensible" arguments based on probability,
expectation, personal experience and the like, whereas logic deals
principally with provable facts and demonstrably valid relations
between them. For example, ad hominem
arguments are logically unsound, but in many cases they may be
rational. A simple philosophical definition of rationality refers
to one's use of a "practical syllogism". For example,
- I am cold
- I don't want to be cold
- If I close the window I will not be cold...
- I don't want to be cold
-
- Therefore, I will close the window
All that is required for an action to be rational
is that if one believes action X (which can be done) implies Y, and
that Y is desirable, he or she does X. The action would likewise be
avoided were Y undesirable. Such arguments are logically valid
but not necessarily logically sound.
For example, the premise "If I close the window I will not be
cold..." may in fact be incorrect. As making formally sound
argument is generally considered
difficult, the "soundness" or "strength" of such premises will
often rest on induction,
statistics, and
simplified heuristical models.
In philosophy, rationality and
reason are the key methods used to analyse the data gathered
through systematically gathered observations. In economics, sociology, and political
science, a decision or situation is often called rational if it
is in some sense optimal, and individuals or organizations are often
called rational if they tend to act somehow optimally in pursuit of
their goals. Thus one speaks, for example, of a rational allocation
of resources, or of a rational corporate strategy. In this concept
of "rationality", the individual's goals or motives are taken for
granted and not made subject to criticism, ethical or otherwise.
Thus rationality simply refers to the success of goal attainment,
whatever those goals may be. Sometimes, in this context,
rationality is equated with behavior that is self-interested to the
point of being selfish. Sometimes rationality implies having
complete knowledge about all the details of a given
situation.
Debates arise in these three fields about whether
or not people or organizations are "really" rational, as well as
whether it make sense to model them as such in formal models. Some
have argued that a kind of bounded
rationality makes more sense for such models. Others think that
any kind of rationality along the lines of rational choice theory
is a useless concept for understanding human behavior; the term
homo
economicus (economic man: the imaginary logically
consistent but amoral being assumed in economic models) was
coined largely in honor of this view.
Rationality is a central principle in artificial
intelligence, where a rational agent is specifically defined as
an agent which always chooses the action which maximises its
expected performance, given all of the knowledge it currently
possesses.
Quality of Rationality
It is believed by most philosophers (A.C
Grayling) and experts, that a good rationale must be independent of
emotions, personal feelings or any kind of instincts. Any process
of evaluation or analysis, that may be called rational, is expected
to be highly objective, logical and "mechanical". If these minimum
requirements are not satisfied i.e. if a person has been, even
slightly, influenced by personal emotions, feelings, instincts or
culturally specific, moral codes and norms, then the analysis may
be termed irrational.
However, it is difficult for most common people
to satisfy these requirement, as it requires a great degree of
intrapersonal intelligence to maintain high standards of immunity
from emotions and a detailed understanding of procedure of
reasoning. Moreover, a number of issues may be analysed by people
who have a very culturally specific understanding of ethics, which
may further make it likely for their opinions to be
irrational.
Theories of rationality
The German sociologist Max Weber
proposed an interpretation of social action that distinguished
between four different types of rationality. The first, which he
called Zweckrational or purposive/instrumental rationality, is
related to the expectations about the behavior of other human
beings or objects in the environment. These expectations serve as
means for a particular actor to attain ends, ends which Weber noted
were "rationally pursued and calculated." The second type, Weber
called Wertrational or value/belief-oriented. Here the action is
undertaken for what one might call reasons intrinsic to the actor:
some ethical, aesthetic, religious or other motive, independent of
whether it will lead to success. The third type was affectual,
determined by an actor's specific affect, feeling, or emotion - to
which Weber himself said that this was a kind of rationality that
was on the borderline of what he considered "meaningfully
oriented." The fourth was traditional, determined by ingrained
habituation. Weber emphasized that it was very unusual to find only
one of these orientations: combinations were the norm. His usage
also makes clear that he considered the first two as more
significant than the others, and it is arguable that the third and
fourth are subtypes of the first two. These kinds of rationality
were ideal types. The advantage in this interpretation is that it
avoids a value-laden assessment, say, that certain kinds of beliefs
are irrational. Instead, Weber suggests that a ground or motive can
be given – for religious or affect reasons, for example — that may
meet the criterion of explanation or justification even if it is
not an explanation that fits the Zweckrational orientation of means
and ends. The opposite is therefore also true: some means-ends
explanations will not satisfy those whose grounds for action are
Wertrational.
Based on the premise that 'feelings of
worthlessness' are a maladaptive byproduct of the evolution of
rationality, Phil Roberts, Jr. has proposed a theory in which the
rationality of an end is presumed to correlate with the
comprehensiveness of its underlying considerations, and in which no
concrete objective is presumed to be rational in any but a relative
sense of the term. In addition to its ability to explain what
morality is (a shared subconscious theory of rationality), Roberts
has also demonstrated how his theory can be employed to address a
number of rationality paradoxes, including the paradox of rational
irrationality, cognitive versus practical rationality conflict, the
"rationality debate" (Cohen vs. Kahneman and Tversky) and the
paradox of the Prisoner's Dilemma.http://www.rationology.net
Use of the term rational
In a number of kinds of speech, "rational" may
also denote a hodge-podge of generally positive attributes,
including:
- reasonable: "having sound judgment and practical implementation" (Webster's)
- reasonable: "not extreme or excessive" (Webster's)
- justifiable on the basis of reason. (logical)
- economical, not wasteful ("rational management," "to rationalize" something)
- not foolish
- coherent
See also
External links and references
- What is rationality?
- Reason and Rationality, by Richard Samuels, Stephen Stich, Luc Faucher on the broad field of reason and rationality from descriptive, normative, and evaluative points of view
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy entry on Historicist Theories of Rationality
- Legal Reasoning After Post-Modern Critiques of Reason, by Peter Suber
- Spohn, W. (2002). The Many Facets of the Theory of Rationality. Croatian Journal of Philosophy 2: 247-262.
- Anand, P (1993). Foundations of Rational Choice Under Risk, Oxford, Oxford University Press
- Nozick, Robert (1993). The Nature of Rationality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
rationality in German: Rationalität
rationality in Spanish: Racionalidad
rationality in French: Rationalité
rationality in Italian: Razionalità
rationality in Norwegian: Rasjonalitet
rationality in Romanian: Raţionalitate
rationality in Finnish:
Rationaalisuus
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
IQ,
Vernunft, admissibility, apprehension, balance, brain, brains, caliber, capacity, common sense,
comprehension,
conception, contact
with reality, cool head, coolheadedness, coolness, deduction, deductive power,
deductive reasoning, demonstration, discourse, discourse of
reason, discursive reason, down-to-earthness, due sense of,
earthiness,
esemplastic power, esprit, freedom from illusion,
good sense, gray matter, hardheadedness, head, headpiece, healthy mind, horse
sense, ideation,
induction, inductive
reasoning, integrative power, intellect, intellection, intellectual
faculty, intellectual grasp, intellectual power, intellectualism,
intellectuality,
intelligence,
intelligence quotient, justifiability, justness, knowledge, lack of feelings,
level head, levelheadedness,
logic, logical thought,
logicality, logicalness, lucid interval,
lucidity,
matter-of-factness, mens,
mental age, mental balance, mental capacity, mental equilibrium,
mental grasp, mental health, mental hygiene, mental poise, mental
ratio, mentality,
mind, mother wit, native
wit, normalcy, normality, normalness, nous, philosophy, plain sense,
plausibility,
positivism, power of
mind, power of reason, practical mind, practical wisdom,
practical-mindedness, practicality, practicalness, pragmaticism, pragmatism, proof, psyche, ratio, ratiocination, rationalism, rationalization,
rationalizing,
realism, reason, reasonability, reasonableness, reasoning, reasoning faculty,
reasoning power, right mind, sanemindedness, saneness, sanity, scientism, scope of mind,
secularism, sense, senses, sensibleness, smarts, sober senses,
sober-mindedness, soberness, sobriety, sophistry, sound mind, sound
sense, soundness,
soundness of mind, specious reasoning, sweet reason, thinking
power, understanding, unidealism, unromanticalness,
unsentimentality,
wholesomeness,
wit, worldliness